Paranormal News

Why Most Research Findings About Psi Are False: The Replicability Crisis, the Psi Paradox and the Myth of Sisyphus – Fro…

Replicability Crisis and Psi Research

The replicability crisis has been illustrated by the results of nine experiments conducted by Bem (2011) and reported in the Journal of Personality and Social Psychology as supporting the existence of precognition. As Romero (2019) explains “although the finding persuaded very few scientists, the controversy engendered mistrust in the ways psychologists conduct their experiments because Bem used procedures and statistical tools that many social psychologists use” (p. 3). Indeed, if Bem was able to demonstrate the existence of precognition – and given that precognition cannot exist for a lot of psychologists (Reber and Alcock, 2020) – did he show unwittingly that something was profoundly wrong in the way experiments are conducted in the field of psychology (Wiggins and Chrisopherson, 2019)? Many relevant papers have been published since Bem’s initial publication (Pashler and Harris, 2012; Savalei and Dunn, 2015) about the replicability crisis, Bayesian statistics (Witte and Zenker, 2017), and questionable research practices (QRPs; Wagenmakers et al., 2011; Bierman et al., 2016). In the present paper, we would like to suggest that this debate could be an opportunity to develop original thinking about psychology and replicability. In this regard, we will show that the Bem studies are not an isolated “accident,” but are actually inserted in a long tradition of research which tries to deal with complex epistemological problems concerning the nature of reality and human consciousness. Specifically, we will argue that the controversies about the existence of psi could be highly informative about psychology and consciousness studies.

Psi research can be considered as a subfield of consciousness studies concerned with interactions between individuals and their environment that transcends the ordinary constraints of space-time (Bem and Honorton, 1994; Radin, 2006; Irwin and Watt, 2007; Cardeña, 2018). Different lines of research have been developed for more than a century to tackle psi using experimental research (Rhine et al., 1966), spontaneous cases (Rhine-Feather and Schmicker, 2005), clinical cases (Rabeyron, 2020), selected participants (Méheust, 1999; Braude, 2007), and applications (Schwartz, 2001, 2007; May et al., 2018). Several meta-analyses of studies conducted under controlled conditions examine precognitive dreams (es = 0.14; Sherwood and Roe, 2003), telepathy (es = 0.14; Storm et al., 2010), and presentiment (es = 0.21; Mossbridge et al., 2012) and have demonstrated statistically significant effects. Bem (2011) research about precognition published in the JPSP is thus not isolated. It can be considered as the logical of evolution of previous psi research.

While these results support the existence of consistent anomalous experience/behavior that has been labeled “psi,” there is currently no consensus in the scientific community concerning their interpretation and two main positions have emerged so far. The “skeptics” suppose that they are the consequences of errors, bias, and different forms of QRPs (Alcock, 2003; Alcock et al., 2003; Hyman, 2010; Wiseman, 2010; Wagenmakers et al., 2011; Reber and Alcock, 2020). The “proponents” argue that these results prove the existence of psi beyond reasonable doubt and that new research should move on to the analysis of psi processes rather than yet more attempts to prove its existence (Radin, 2006; Cardeña et al., 2015; Cardeña, 2018). This absence of consensus is related to the difficulty of drawing firm conclusions from the results of psi research. Indeed, they represent an anomaly (Rao and Palmer, 1987) because there is currently no scientific model – based on physical or biology principles – to explain such interactions even if they exist (Kuhn, 1962). Nevertheless, which ever explanation is correct, the results of psi research may be informative for the wider psychological sciences (Schooler et al., 2018). Indeed, they lead to two opposites but very heuristic hypothesis: (a) within this domain of research, which has been conducted by hundreds of researchers whose critical efforts span over a century, the researchers have either been fraudulent or have been fooled, even when using the most reliable tools of scientific research and (b) psi exists and human consciousness can interact with its environment beyond the usual boundaries of space and time. This paper will explore these two hypotheses and their consequences for psi research and psychology in general.

What if… Psi Really Exists? The Psi Paradox

History of science has shown many examples of phenomena that were observed in a reliable manner but which were rejected by the scientific community because they were not explainable at the time of their observation (e.g., meteorites, heartbeat, etc.). Consequently, it might be wise to be careful when considering anomalous results of the psi variety, especially knowing that 22 Nobel Prize winners, leading scientists, and figures of the intellectual life have reported such experiences and took a position in favor of their existence (Méheust, 1999). Thus, if we suppose – at least for a moment – that there are enough elements to take seriously the hypothesis that the (b) option is true, that is, psi really exists, what are the consequences of such an assumption? Could it make sense of other observations in the field of psychology and other scientific domains? And does it change the way scientific research should be conducted?

The psi studies, viewed as a whole, suggest that a kind of “direct” interaction (conscious or unconscious) between individual humans and their environment is possible. This interaction concerns events or objects situated at a distance in space and time (Mossbridge and Radin, 2018). It can take many forms (gut feeling, behavior, mental representation, etc.) with different intensities (e.g., a small or a strong emotion). It can be perceptive (from the environment to the person) or projective (from the person to the environment). It can be associated with a transfer of information or, rather, something that looks like a transfer of information (Lucadou et al., 2007). It emerges more easily during altered states of consciousness (Storm et al., 2010), is more pronounced for some persons (Schlitz and Honorton, 1992), and tends to emerge during or after traumatic events (Rabeyron and Loose, 2015). This direct interaction is more generally associated with subjective paranormal experiences (e.g., near death experiences and out of body experiences) even if they do not overlap entirely (Rabeyron et al., 2018). Moreover, even if the role of consciousness in psi processes is not well understood, it is likely that attention (McMoneagle and May, 2014), memory (Carpenter, 2012), creativity (Holt, 2012), personality traits (Thalbourne, 2000), belief (Lawrence, 1993), and psychodynamic aspects (Rabeyron and Loose, 2015) are components of it.

These results from psi research construct a specific paradox that is the crux of the present paper. This paradox would lead to the conclusion that most research findings in psi research are false (or inappropriate) but not for the reasons usually supposed by the skeptics. We need first to recall that scientific research is based on the principle that, in the main, the researcher (the observer) is separated from, or independent of, the dependent variable. The researcher tries not to affect the result of an experiment so that what is observed varies with the independent variable being tested and is independent of the researcher’s thoughts, intentions, belief, or disbelief. This assumption is assumed to permit other scientists to demonstrate the same result under the same conditions (or not, as the case may be). This is the logical and epistemological frame in which scientific research is usually conducted. This model works very well and has produced much reliable scientific knowledge and technological progress. Even if this is a simplistic vision of the way scientific research progresses, as shown by epistemology of science (Feyerabend, 1975; Chalmers, 1979), such a representation of scientific research is nevertheless a useful principle, which guides scientists to good practice.

However, if a direct interaction (in the sense described above) between a person and their environment is possible, this principle too could influence the outcome of experiments purporting to use the scientific principles, because there could be a direct interaction between the scientists (the observer) and their object of study (the observed). Thus, if psi exists, the problem is the following: an advertent or inadvertent “direct” interaction between the researcher and the object of study could be possible. This destroys the conditions necessary for the convincing scientific demonstration of psi itself.

This leads to the following paradoxs: (1) if the existence of psi is proven in a classical scientific setting, then it demonstrates retroactively that this setting is inappropriate because psi implies that there is no clear “cut” between the observer and the observed. (2) So, if this assumption of the scientific setting is inappropriate (because of psi), then this setting cannot be used to prove the existence of psi. But, then, as psi cannot be proven, the scientific setting itself appears as being still appropriate! Consequently, we can try to use the scientific setting to prove the existence of psi but then we are now again at (1), which leads to (2), and it logically follows an infinite paradoxical loop between (1) and (2). It shows more generally that the principle on which a scientific experiment is based to study psi – the ontological separation between the observer and the observed – would be erroneous. Consequently, any scientific knowledge in this field of research could not be produced as soon as there is no clear distinction between the observer and the observed. Indeed, there is no way to know, for epistemological reasons, if what is observed is an effect induced by the experimenter (due to a possible psi influence) or a characteristic of the phenomena independently of the experimenter. The distinction between expectations and reality is then unclear, and the psi researcher using this approach can only become a modern version of Sisyphus as it will be shown later.

Two Examples From the Literature: the Ganzfeld Protocol and the Bem Studies

The Ganzfeld experiment – the most classical protocol in psi research (Bem and Honorton, 1994) – provides an interesting example of the previous reasoning. During this experiment, a participant (the receiver) is comfortably seated in a chair, wearing a mask showing him a uniform visual field (usually red) while listening to a white noise. The participant is immersed in a constant and neutral sensory field that rapidly engenders an altered state of consciousness supposed to favor psi perceptions (Storm et al., 2010). After 20 min, the participant tries to find, among several images or videos (usually, the correct target and three alternate targets), the one that was “transmitted” telepathically by another participant (the sender) located in another room. As shown by the literature, an average success rate of 33% in the receiver’s choice has been obtained instead of 25% by chance alone (Storm et al., 2010). A significant correlation between the choices of the receivers and the targets shown to the senders has thus been demonstrated. But what else has been learned and does this experiment demonstrate the existence of telepathy?

No, because it cannot be proven in a definite manner. Different competing interpretations could be proposed but they cannot be isolated or confirmed. There is indeed no way to propose a falsifiable claim or set-up a crucial experiment (Popper, 1934). For example, is it a telepathic effect (the target is “sent” by the sender and “received” by the receiver) or a precognitive effect (the receiver actually perceives the target from the “future,” when presented with the four possible targets at the end of the session and asked to choose)? To test this hypothesis, an experiment can be set-up in which a feedback is given to half of the receivers (they see the correct target after the Ganzfeld state) and no feedback is given to half of the receivers (they do not see the correct target and, instead, a blind judge evaluates the correlation between the receiver’s mentations and the four possible targets). If we suppose that a significant effect is obtained only for feedback trials, does it prove the precognitive hypothesis? Not so, because even if this experiment was replicated 50 times with the same results and using the best experimental conditions, there is no way to know if this effect is a consequence of (1) a precognitive effect, (2) a psi influence from the participants, (3) a psi effect from the experimenter on the computer that chooses the target, and (4) many other options! Because as soon as there is no clear cut between the experimenter, the participant, and the methodology, everything becomes possible.

Another possibility is that some experimenters are consistently able to influence the experimental data and so gain significant results. This variable itself has been the focus of considerable research (Broughton, 1979; Palmer, 1997; Parker and Miller, 2014). It can be tested during a Ganzfeld experiment by working with 10 different experimenters and by comparing their results. But even if a correlation between (for example) the experimenter’s belief (a measure of its possible psi influence on the setup) and the Ganzfeld effect size is found, no clear conclusion could be reached. It could be (1) the effect of the experimenter, (2) the effect of the analyst of the study (the one who look at the data first), or (3) many other potential explanations! This is again the same problem: if there is no clear cut between the experimenter, the participants, and the scientific set-up, there is no falsifiable claim. Importantly, this problem is infinite: when new variables are introduced, without a clearly falsifiable hypothesis (due to the absence of an epistemological boundary between the observer and what is observed), the problem exists. This lack of clear attributable causation is relevant to the results of most psi experiments and that’s why the psi effects are probably not what they look like. They can be considered as inconclusive from a scientific point of view. Thus, there is no way to be sure that the Ganzfeld is a transfer of information between two people or that precognition is the ability to extract information from the future. Psi studies actually just show that significant correlations between two variables – an intention and a measure – will emerge and take different forms depending on the conditions of the experimental setting.

The recent experiments reported by Bem (2011) on the anomalous anticipation of random events illustrate perfectly the problem we have just described. Bem (2011), publishing in a mainstream psychological journal, the Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, presented the results of four classical psychology experiments (e.g., priming task) that he has “reversed” in order to see if the participants would be influenced by stimuli not from the past but from the future. This publication induced considerable controversy between skeptics and proponents in the academic community and even in several mainstream media (Bem et al., 2011; Wagenmakers et al., 2011; Ritchie et al., 2012). We can sum up the different steps of this research paradigm: (1) Bem (2011) shows a seemingly reliable psi effect in controlled condition. It engenders critical reactions from the mainstream community (Wagenmakers et al., 2011). In a way, these critics are right: they probably “feel” that it does not look like a classical effect and maybe understand intuitively the potential consequences of this result for the whole field of psychology. (2) The experiment is then replicated in different settings (online, different populations, different stimuli, etc.). Sometimes it works, sometimes it does not work (Galak et al., 2012; Ritchie et al., 2012). (3) A meta-analysis is finally published with a significant, but smaller effect size (es = 0.14), than the original publication (es = 0.20; Bem et al., 2015). Is it because: (a) the effect actually does not exist; (b) the setting of the new experiments was less appropriate; (c) the replication process in itself decreases the effect? (Lucadou, 1995; Kennedy, 2003); or (d) the effect is actually the consequence of an experimenter effect described above? (Kennedy and Taddonio, 1976; Broughton, 1979; Palmer, 1997; Smith, 2003; Parker and Miller, 2014). A fourth step is thus necessary; and (4) a new study is concurrently conducted in different labs to study the impact of experimenter’s individual differences on the results. But this effect could actually depend on the analyst (i.e., the one who look at the results for the first time or analyze the data) and not the experimenter (West and Fisk, 1953). So, the next step of this research paradigm might be (5) to test the magnitude of the effect with 10 different experimenters and 10 different analysts.

These different steps show the possible impediments which plague psi researchers in their efforts to prove the existence of psi, in addition to negative results and criticism from mainstream colleagues. And even if the researcher manages to get significant results at every step – as done by Bem (2011) for many years –, there will always be new demands from the mainstream community: more control of the experimental setting, more experiments, more labs, more statistical tools, etc., (Wagenmakers et al., 2015). Even when proponents manage to agree a clear protocol with skeptics, and then obtain significant results, which has been the case with the Ganzfeld (Hyman and Honorton, 1986; Bem and Honorton, 1994), it is never enough. The underlying problem is that even if a significant effect is found at each step, there is no way to conclude anything about the nature of the effect and consequently no way to produce scientific knowledge about the source of psi (Broughton, 1979; Palmer, 1997): is it from the participants? From the experimenter? Is it from each experimenter separately? Or is it a stronger influence from the first one who analyze the data? Or, maybe that the one who has originally conceived the experiment? Are there degrees of influence between the experimenter and the participants depending on the type of experiment? But also, is it an effect in the present (during the experiment) or is it an influence from the future (after the experiment), or even the past, if psi can transcend space and time? There are no definite answers to these questions, whatever results are obtained and unfortunately, there is, to our knowledge, no way to answer these questions because there are only plausible interpretations. Fundamentally, the problem is that the usual epistemological frame of research is not adequate when considering psi proprieties.

In this regard, it might be relevant to stop doing research whose aim is to prove the existence of psi using classical (scientific method) setting, because it does not really make sense from an epistemological point of view. It may be argued that this methodology cannot produce anything new even with large financing and the passage of a century of research. Nevertheless, these experiments are relevant in terms of ritual. A selection of classical psi experiments can be used – e.g., the Ganzfeld, dreams or presentiment studies – as illustrations of a phenomena, recognizing their “limitations” and without believing that something new explanation will be emerge from them. If they are conducted with enough intention, motivation, novelty, and creativity, these experiments should continue to produce significant results. Their interest is mainly strategic because it gives the opportunity to show that psi can be replicated and produce significant effects in controlled conditions as shown by several meta-analysis (Cardeña, 2018).

Nevertheless, these “demonstration studies” might even be more complicated if we also take into account that psi effects tend to disappear when the same experiment is replicated, which is described as the elusive nature of psi (Hansen, 2001; Kennedy, 2003). When a psi experiment is set-up, a distinction between two variables or a hypothesis is proposed (true/false). If another experiment uses the same hypothesis, many researchers have reported that the effect tends to disappear (Kennedy, 2003). In this regard, using the same hypothesis twice for a psi experiment could be like asking a comedian trying to make the public laugh with the same joke twice. Psi interactions seem to be the expression of a novelty and novelty, by definition, can be new only once. It might explain the strange results – inversion, displacement, and disappearance of the effect – that appear when the same experiment is replicated (Lucadou, 1995). In order to avoid this difficulty, and following the Sisyphus metaphor, some researchers take a small rock (an experiment), push it up the mountain, and then do this with another rock (another experiment), but they do not push the same rock twice to avoid too much “resistance” that would result from the replication of the same experiment. They do not do this because the effect does not exist, as suggested by Wiseman (2010), but as the consequence of the fact that this is the only way to maintain the effect.

Due to these different epistemological difficulties, new knowledge in the field of psi research based on “classical” protocol would not be reliable and even those related to the understanding of psi processes. For example, if personality traits are correlated with psi, how to be sure this is not the consequence of the psi influence from the experimenter about which personality traits he believes favor psi? This is the same for all parameters that could be correlated with psi results. These researches cannot produce scientific knowledge and so may be considered as a waste of time and energy in the same way as Sisyphus spends all his time doing a useless and infinite task. Some researchers in the field have recognized this problem and have stopped doing this kind of experimental research (Eisenbud, 1966, 1983). Others understand this problem and try to find a way to avoid it with specific experimental set-up (Lucadou et al., 2007; Walach and von Stillfried, 2011). Others acknowledge this problem but continue to do experimental research like this because this approach is relevant from a “political” and strategic point of view (Radin, 2018). They know intuitively how to conduct experiments in order to keep “alive” a psi effect in spite of its profoundly elusive nature. They suppose that these experiments can be useful to convince the whole scientific community, and a larger audience, if they are conducted in a sufficient rigorous way. This could be considered as a pragmatic approach using the wrong tools to show something that might be true. And other researchers do not understand this problem and continue to do this kind of research, in the same manner as Rhine (1966) used to do, because they do not feel that there are other options. It would be like a woodsman trying to fell trees with a feather saying that he continues to do so because this is the only tool he has. If they are lucky, despite the inappropriate nature of the research methodology, they will occasionally obtain significant results, but will also obtain null results. If they are resilient, they will do this during all their careers and become Sisyphus, trying to convince a scientific community who do not believe in the existence of what they study. Not surprisingly, some of them will stop doing parapsychological research and even can become skeptic (Blackmore, 1987).

Replicability Crisis, Decline Effect, and Psi

As mentioned in the introduction, psychology and medicine have been confronted for more than 10 years by what has been called the replication or replicability crisis (Maxwell et al., 2015). It shows that the magnitude of the effect sizes in replications of psychology experiments is half the size of the original studies and that only 36% of the effect may be replicable (Nosek et al., 2015). The same problem is also true for other domains, especially medical and psychotherapy research (Ioannidis, 2016a,b). This is, of course, a huge problem that many researchers are trying to solve. One of the hypotheses to explain this situation is that these results could be the consequence of QRPs (John et al., 2012) and that most of these studies would not have been significant if they had been carried out with more rigor (Simmons et al., 2011). Consequently, the conduct of “Science” has to change by improving using – notably – pre-registration, better statistics, and the publication of null results.

The replication crisis has also underlined a phenomenon calls the “decline effect” (Schooler, 2011; Simmons et al., 2011; Protzko and Schooler, 2017). It shows that different effects in psychology and medicine tend to diminish with time and replication process e.g., (see Coyne and de Voogd, 2012; Gong and Jiao, 2019). In this regard, it is interesting to note that the psi community has reported such a decline effect a long time ago (Kennedy, 2003). Is it the same effect and what is its nature? Most researchers suppose that it is also the consequence of QRP but a different hypothesis could be proposed; the underlying problem of this decline effect might be psi, if the latter exists. It means that a direct relationship between an intention and reality is possible. Consequently, when mainstream research is set-up, psi might come in the equation even if it is not invited to the party. When researchers develop a new protocol or hypothesis, their expectations or intentions might, through psi, unconsciously induce a result which favors their view. Thus, when a new effect or a new treatment is tested – with, for example, a control group – the researcher might have a psi influence at various points in the research design, which could compromise the utility of the control group as a comparison condition.

As an example of how this unexpected influence could might affect data, May (1995) has developed the decision augmentation theory (DAT) to explain the results of studies in which participants had to influence, solely by intention, the output of a random number generator (Bösch et al., 2006). May supposes that there is no physical influence in this process and that the participant, using precognitive abilities, will choose (unconsciously) the right moment to push the button in order to get desired significant result. In the same way, a researcher might unconsciously choose the right moment to start the study, choose the participants, collect the data, etc., in order to induce an effect in randomness. From this point of view, psi does not induce a transfer of energy or rely on a known physical force. It rather organizes reality in a discreet manner by ordering randomness. Consequently, some of the mainstream effects look like normal effects but they are not. It is only when other researchers – who may not have the same expectations, beliefs, or intentions – try to replicate them that these effects may mysteriously vanish. This would not be the effect of QRP, but the consequence of psi.

It could be argued that if this hypothesis is true, there is no possibility of accumulating any reliable scientific knowledge. But this is not the case because all observed effects are not attributable to psi; the latter acts as an “extended placebo” – that is, beyond the classical conception of placebo influence, see Lucadou, 2019 – that produce unexpected fluctuations in the data. But when a “real” and robust effect is replicated by different teams of researchers, it should resist if this is not a psi effect, and this might be what happened during the reproducibility project (Nosek et al., 2015). Thus, it is still possible to demonstrate the existence of “established,” “real,” or “classical” effects, laws, or forces (which probably concern the vast majority of reality) and, in this regard, the scientific model is still totally relevant. But it means that effect sizes around 0.10 and 0.20 – the usual magnitude reported in the psi literature – in experiments within many scientific domains, might actually be the consequence of psi.

The other interpretation of psi data – that psi does not exist, the “null hypothesis” (Alcock, 2003) – is also interesting from a psychological and sociological point of view. As proposed in introduction, it would suggest that hundreds of researchers (and notably more than 20 Nobel Prize winners) have been fooled for more than a century, even when using the most reliable tools of scientific research. The effect of these “illusory” results have been so convincing that they even led to practical applications (Schwartz, 2007; Mossbridge et al., 2014). For example, the United States government attempted to employ psi for more than 20 years during a program usually known as Stargate in which military personnel were selected on basis of their supposed psi-abilities to acquire information (e.g., about Russian military sites) at a distance (in space and time; Hyman, 1996; Utts, 1996; May et al., 2018). The null hypothesis would mean that staff of the best United States intelligence agencies (CIA, NSA, etc.), a number of military officers working on this program (some of whom were decorated with the legion of merit; McMoneagle and May, 2014), top scientists who have examined the project (notably a past president of the American Statistical Association; Utts, 1996), and even the president of the United States (Jimmy Carter admitted that a lost military plane Tu-22 has been found thanks to the Stargate program) have been fooled by the results of 504 military operations over almost 20 years (1973–1995). If this interpretation of significant results in psi experiments is accepted, it may follow that other areas of “reputable” research, involving many researchers, could also produce illusory results.

To Conclude: Perspectives for Future Research

Psi studies are particularly interesting because whatever the reaction to the question “does psi exist?” (Bem and Honorton, 1994), their results affect the whole of psychology. If psi does not exist, significant results for nearly a century have only been obtained by methodological errors, self-deception, fraud, and questionable research practices. How could we avoid such a problem? Since the beginning of the replicability crisis, several solutions have been proposed – pre-registration of study designs, Bayesian statistics, larger N, funnel plots, p-curve analysis, prospective meta-analysis, adversial collaborations, etc., (Bateman et al., 2005) – which could show, at the end, non-significant results in the field of psi studies, revealing that psi was only an illusion. A pre-registration registry has already been set-up in the field of psi research (Watt and Kennedy, 2015, 2017, 2019) as well as statistical guidelines for empirical studies (Tressoldi and Utts, 2015; Kennedy, 2016; Utts and Tressoldi, 2019). Pre-submission to scientific journals which accept a paper on methodological grounds prior to results should also be promoted. In this regard, a “transparent psi project” is currently being conducted which follows these recommendations. Such an approach might be extended to other psi paradigms to confirm or deny the significant results of several meta-analysis (Sherwood and Roe, 2003; Storm et al., 2010; Mossbridge et al., 2012).

On the contrary, if psi does exist, it means that human consciousness can interact with its environment beyond the usual boundaries of space and time, which has fundamental consequences for the way research is conducted in psychology, including psi research (as demonstrated by the psi paradox). As already mentioned, the results of experimental psi research have shown, since their beginning, strange patterns in the data (displacement, reversal, etc.) called notably psi-missing (Rhine, 1952) and elusiveness (Kennedy, 2003). A solution might be to consider these patterns not as an obstacle – or just the effect of randomness (Wiseman, 2010) – but rather as a way to better understand psi and its properties. Following this idea, an original line of research has been initiated by the physicist and psychologist Walter Von Lucadou with the “Model of Pragmatic Information” (MPI; Lucadou, 1995; Lucadou et al., 2007). In this model, psi is considered as being something profoundly different to known macro-physical effects and causation, not relying on transfer of information but rather a form of entanglement process depending on the underlying nature of reality (Atmanspacher and Fuchs, 2017; Atmanspacher and Fach, 2019). A brief metaphor might be useful here. A psi experiment is like an egg where the shell forms an enclosed organizational system. It may be possible to maintain a psi effect as long as the organizational closure is not broken, that is as long as the egg is not broken to see what is inside. In this interpretation, the psi interactions are possible as long as the observer does not interfere with the system (Houtkooper, 2002). Once the system is observed, “the game is over.” This would explain why the source of psi cannot be determined precisely because the determination process would destroy the necessary conditions for the emergence of psi. It also underlines the importance of uncertainty associated with the source of psi. When the latter is used for a transfer of information, the psi effect would be suppressed, especially when attempts are made to replicate exactly the same experimental set. This is what Lucadou calls the “Non-Transmission Axiom” (Lucadou et al., 2007).

Consequently, Lucadou has tried to set-up an experiment in which this type of effect might be maintained by keeping a sufficient level of uncertainty in the system. This experiment uses the “Correlation Matrix Method” (CMM) in which the global number of correlations between the participants and an experimental task (associated with a RNG) is predicted, but not the location of such correlations in the correlational matrix (Lucadou, 2015; Flores et al., 2018; Walach et al., 2019). The non-transmission axiom could also explain the decline effect and the oscillating trends in the data (Pallikari and Boller, 1997; Maier et al., 2018; Maier and Dechamps, 2018). This last aspect is particularly interesting because these oscillating patterns might be detected, demonstrated, and analyzed when they are compared with classical effects (Rabeyron, 2014).

This line of research appears as an interesting example of what could be conceived as an example of “postmodern psychology” which takes into account the complexity of human consciousness, and more precisely postulates a potential entanglement between the observer and what is observed. It also shows how psi might be implicated in the “hard problem” of consciousness (Chalmers, 2007) or the “problem of measurement” (Wigner, 1963). Even if the possibility that psi exists sounds very implausible to many (Wiseman, 2010; Reber and Alcock, 2020), and as proposed recently by Schooler et al. (2018), a neutral and respectful approach to this topic might open heuristic debates within the wider field of psychology concerning the replicability crisis and the nature of consciousness.

Data Availability Statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Footnotes

References

Alcock, J. E. (2003). Give the null hypothesis a chance: reasons to remain doubtful about the existence of psi. J. Conscious. Stud. 10, 29–50.

Google Scholar

Alcock, J. E., Burns, J., and Freeman, A. (2003). Psi wars: Getting to grips with the paranormal. Charlottesville: Imprint Academic.

Google Scholar

Atmanspacher, H., and Fach, W. (2019). Exceptional experiences of stable and unstable mental states, understood from a dual-aspect point of view. Philosophies 4:7. doi: 10.3390/philosophies4010007

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Atmanspacher, H., and Fuchs, C. A. (2017). The Pauli-Jung conjecture and its impact today. London: Andrews UK Limited.

Google Scholar

Bateman, I., Kahneman, D., Munro, A., Starmer, C., and Sugden, R. (2005). Testing competing models of loss aversion: an adversarial collaboration. J. Public Econ. 89, 1561–1580. doi: 10.1016/j.jpubeco.2004.06.013

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bem, D., and Honorton, C. (1994). Does psi exist? Replicable evidence for an anomalous process of information transfer. Psychol. Bull. 115, 4–18. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.115.1.4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bem, D., Tressoldi, P., Rabeyron, T., and Duggan, M. (2015). Feeling the future: a meta-analysis of 90 experiments on the anomalous anticipation of random future events. F1000Res 4:1188. doi: 10.12688/f1000research.7177.2

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bierman, D. J. (2000). Anomalous baseline effects in mainstream emotion research using psychophysiological variables. J. Parapsychol. 64:239.

Google Scholar

Bierman, D. J., and Rabeyron, T. (2012). “Can psi research sponsor itself? Simulations and results of an automated ARV-casino experiment.” in Paper presented at the 56st annual convention of the parapsychological association.

Google Scholar

Bierman, D. J., Spottiswoode, J. P., and Bijl, A. (2016). Testing for questionable research practices in a meta-analysis: an example from experimental parapsychology. PLoS One 11:e0153049. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0153049

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Blackmore, S. (1987). The elusive open mind: ten years of negative research in parapsychology. Skeptical Inquirer 11, 244–255.

Google Scholar

Bösch, H., Steinkamp, F., and Boller, E. (2006). Examining psychokinesis: the interaction of human intention with random number generators–a meta-analysis. Psychol. Bull. 132, 497–523. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.132.4.497

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Braude, S. E. (2007). The gold leaf lady and other parapsychological investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Google Scholar

Broughton, R. S. (1979). Repeatability and experimenter effect: are subjects really necessary? Parapsychol. Rev. 10, 11–14.

Google Scholar

Cardeña, E. (2019). Errors of the third kind. J. Parapsychol. 83, 117–120.

Google Scholar

Cardeña, E., Palmer, J., and Marcusson-Clavertz, D. (2015). Parapsychology: A handbook for the 21st century. Jefferson: McFarland.

Google Scholar

Carpenter, J. C. (2012). First sight: ESP and parapsychology in everyday life. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

Google Scholar

Chalmers, D. (2007). “The hard problem of consciousness” in The Blackwell companion to consciousness. eds. S. Schneider and M. Velmans (Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell).

Google Scholar

Chalmers, A. F. (1979). What is this thing called science?: An assessment of the nature and status of science and its methods. St. Lucia: University of Queensland Press.

Google Scholar

Coyne, J. C., and de Voogd, J. N. (2012). Are we witnessing the decline effect in the Type D personality literature? What can be learned? J. Psychosom. Res. 73, 401–407. doi: 10.1016/j.jpsychores.2012.09.016

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eagleman, D. M., Kagan, A. D., Nelson, S. S., Sagaram, D., and Sarma, A. K. (2007). A standardized test battery for the study of synesthesia. J. Neurosci. Methods 159, 139–145. doi: 10.1016/j.jneumeth.2006.07.012

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eisenbud, J. (1966). The world of Ted serios: “Thoughtographic” studies of an extraordinary mind. New York: William Morrow.

Google Scholar

Eisenbud, J. (1983). Parapsychology and the unconscious. New York: North Atlantic Book.

Google Scholar

Feyerabend, P. (1975). Contre la méthode. Paris: Le Seuil.

Google Scholar

Filk, T., and Römer, H. (2011). Generalized quantum theory: overview and latest developments. Axiomathes 21, 211–230. doi: 10.1007/s10516-010-9136-6

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Flores, A. B., Tierney, I., and Watt, C. A. (2018). Where mind connects with matter: replicating the correlation matrix method. J. Parapsychol. 82, 107–108.

Google Scholar

Hansel, C. E. M. (1961). A critical analysis of the Pearce-Pratt experiment. J. Parapsychol. 25, 87–91.

Google Scholar

Hansen, G. (2001). The trickster and the paranormal. Philadelphia: Xilibiris Corporation.

Google Scholar

Holt, N. (2012). “The muse in the machine: creativity, anomalous experiences and mental health” in Exceptional experience and health. ed. C. Simmonds-Moore (Jefferson: McFarland).

Google Scholar

Houtkooper, J. M. (2002). Arguing for an observational theory of paranormal phenomena. J. Sci. Explor. 16, 171–185.

Google Scholar

Hyland, M. E. (2003). Extended network generalized entanglement theory: therapeutic mechanisms, empirical predictions, and investigations. J. Altern. Complement. Med. 9, 919–936. doi: 10.1089/107555303771952262

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hyman, R. (1996). Evaluation of a program on anomalous mental phenomena. J. Sci. Explor. 10, 321–352.

Google Scholar

Hyman, R. (2010). “Parapsychology’s achilles heel: persistent inconsistency” in Debating psychic experience. eds. S. Krippner and H. L. Friedman (Santa Barbara: Praeger).

Google Scholar

Hyman, R., and Honorton, C. (1986). A joint communiqué: the psi ganzfeld controversy. J. Parapsychol. 50, 351–364.

Google Scholar

Ioannidis, J. P. (2016a). Most psychotherapies do not really work, but those that might work should be assessed in biased studies. Epidemiol. Psychiatr. Sci. 25, 436–438. doi: 10.1017/S2045796015000888

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Irwin, H. J., and Watt, C. (2007). An introduction to parapsychology. Jefferson: McFarland.

Google Scholar

John, L. K., Loewenstein, G., and Prelec, D. (2012). Measuring the prevalence of questionable research practices with incentives for truth telling. Psychol. Sci. 23, 524–532. doi: 10.1177/0956797611430953

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kandel, E. R. (2007). In search of memory: The emergence of a new science of mind. New York: Norton & Company.

Google Scholar

Kennedy, J. E. (2003). The capricious, actively evasive, unsustainable nature of psi: a summary and hypotheses. J. Parapsychol. 67, 53–74.

Google Scholar

Kennedy, J. E. (2016). Is the methodological revolution in psychology over or just beginning. J. Parapsychol. 80, 156–168.

Google Scholar

Kennedy, J. E., and Taddonio, J. L. (1976). Experimenter effects in parapsychological research. J. Parapsychol. 40, 1–33.

Google Scholar

Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago press.

Google Scholar

Lakens, D. (2015). Why a meta-analysis of 90 precognition studies does not provide convincing evidence of a true effect. The Winnower, 6.

Google Scholar

Lawrence, T. R. (1993). “Gathering in the sheep and goats: a meta-analysis of forced-choice sheep-goat ESP studies, 1947–1993.” in Paper presented at the 36st Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association; 1993, Parapsychological Association.

Google Scholar

Lucadou, W. (1995). The model of pragmatic information (MPI). Eur. J. Parapsychol. 11, 58–75.

Google Scholar

Lucadou, W. (2015). “The correlation matrix method (CMM): A new light upon the repeatability problem in parapsychology.” in Paper for the 58th Annual Convention of the Parapsychological Association and the 39th SPR International Conference; 2015, Parapsychological Association.

Google Scholar

Lucadou, W. (2019). Homeopathy and the action of meaning: a theoretical approach. J. Sci. Explor. 33, 213–254. doi: 10.31275/2019.1343

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lucadou, W., Romer, H., and Walach, H. (2007). Synchronistic phenomena as entanglement correlations in generalized quantum theory. J. Conscious. Stud. 14, 50–74.

Google Scholar

Maier, M. A., and Dechamps, M. C. (2018). Observer effects on quantum randomness: testing micro-psychokinetic effects of smokers on addiction-related stimuli. J. Sci. Explor. 32, 265–297. doi: 10.31275/2018.1250

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Maier, M. A., Dechamps, M. C., and Pflitsch, M. (2018). Intentional observer effects on quantum randomness: a Bayesian analysis reveals evidence against micro-psychokinesis. Front. Psychol. 9:379. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00379

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Maxwell, S. E., Lau, M. Y., and Howard, G. S. (2015). Is psychology suffering from a replication crisis? What does “failure to replicate” really mean? Am. Psychol. 70, 487–498. doi: 10.1037/a0039400

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

May, E. C., Marwaha, S. B., Broughton, F., Cohen, W. S., and Broughton, R. S. (2018). The star gate archives: Reports of the United States government sponsored psi program, 1972–1995: Volume 1: Remote viewing, 1972–1984. Jefferson: McFarland & Company.

Google Scholar

May, E. C., Spottiswoode, S., and Faith, L. (2000). The correlation of the gradient of Shannon entropy and anomalous cognition: toward an AC sensory system. J. Sci. Explor. 14, 53–72.

Google Scholar

May, E. C., Utts, J. M., and Spottiswoode, S. J. P. (1995). Decision augmentation theory: applications to the random number generator database. J. Sci. Explor. 9, 453–488.

Google Scholar

McMoneagle, J. W., and May, E. C. (2014). “The possible role of intention, attention and expectation in remote viewing” in Anomalous cognition: Remote viewing research and theory. eds. E. C. May and S. B. Marwaha (Jefferson: McFarland), 368–376.

Google Scholar

Méheust, B. (1999). Somnambulisme et mediumnité. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond.

Google Scholar

Méheust, B. (2003). Un voyant prodigieux: Alexis Didier (1826–1866). Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond.

Google Scholar

Mossbridge, J. A., and Radin, D. (2018). Precognition as a form of prospection: a review of the evidence. Psychol. Conscious. 5, 78–93. doi: 10.1037/cns0000121

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mossbridge, J., Tressoldi, P., and Utts, J. (2012). Predictive physiological anticipation preceding seemingly unpredictable stimuli: a meta-analysis. Front. Psychol. 3:390. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00390

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mossbridge, J., Tressoldi, P. E., Utts, J., Ives, J., Radin, D., and Jonas, W. (2014). Predicting the unpredictable: critical analysis and practical implications of predictive anticipatory activity. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8:146. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00146

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nosek, B. A., Aarts, A. A., Anderson, C. J., Anderson, J. E., and Kappes, H. B. Open Science Collaboration (2015). Estimating the reproducibility of psychological science. Science 349:aac4716. doi: 10.1126/science.aac4716

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pallikari, F., and Boller, E. (1997). Further evidence for a statistical balancing in probabilistic systems influenced by the anomalous effect of conscious intention. J. Soc. Psychol. Res. 62, 114–137.

Google Scholar

Palmer, J. (1997). The challenge of experimenter psi. Eur. J. Parapsychol. 13, 110–125.

Google Scholar

Palmer, J. (2016). Hansel’s ghost: resurrection of the experimenter fraud hypothesis in parapsychology. J. Parapsychol. 80, 5–16.

Google Scholar

Parker, A., and Millar, B. (2014). Revealing psi secrets: successful experimenters seem to succeed by using their own psi. J. Parapsychol. 78, 39–55.

Google Scholar

Popper, K. (1934). The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Protzko, J., and Schooler, J. W. (2017). “Decline effects: types, mechanisms, and personal reflections” in Psychological science under scrutiny: Recent challenges and proposed solutions. eds. S. O. Lilienfeld and I. D. Waldman (New Yersey: Wiley-Blackwell).

Google Scholar

Rabeyron, T. (2020). Clinique des expériences exceptionnelles. Paris: Dunod.

Google Scholar

Rabeyron, T., and Loose, T. (2015). Anomalous experiences, trauma, and symbolization processes at the Frontiers between psychoanalysis and cognitive neurosciences. Front. Psychol. 6:1926. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01926

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rabeyron, T., Rowe, C., Mousseau, M. C., and Deledalle, A. (2018). Anomalous experiences, mental health, and creativity: is psi the missing link? J. Conscious. Stud. 25, 207–232.

Google Scholar

Rabeyron, T., and Watt, C. (2010). Paranormal experiences, mental health and mental boundaries, and psi. Pers. Individ. Differ. 48, 487–492. doi: 10.1016/j.paid.2009.11.029

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Radin, D. (2006). Entangled minds: Extrasensory experiences in a quantum reality. New York: Paraview Pocket Books.

Google Scholar

Radin, D. (2018). Real magic: Ancient wisdom, modern science, and a guide to the secret power of the universe. New York: Harmony.

Google Scholar

Rao, K. R., and Palmer, J. (1987). The anomaly called psi: recent research and criticism. Behav. Brain Sci. 10, 539–551. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X00054455

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rhine, J. B. (1952). The problem of psi-missing. J. Parapsychol. 16, 90–129.

Google Scholar

Rhine, J. B., Pratt, J. G., Smith, B. M., Stuart, C. E., and Greenwood, J. A. (1966). Extra-sensory perception after sixty years. Boston: Bruce Humphries Publishers.

Google Scholar

Rhine-Feather, S., and Schmicker, M. (2005). The gift: The extraordinary experiences of ordinary people. New York: St. Martin’s Paperbacks.

Google Scholar

Ritchie, S. J., Wiseman, R., and French, C. C. (2012). Failing the future: three unsuccessful attempts to replicate bem’s ‘retroactive facilitation of recall’ effect. PLoS One 7:e33423. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0033423

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schlitz, M. J., and Honorton, C. (1992). Ganzfeld psi performance within an artistically gifted population. J. Am. Soc. Psychol. Res. 86, 83–98.

Google Scholar

Schlitz, M. J., Wiseman, R., Watt, C., and Radin, D. (2006). Of two minds: skeptic-proponent collaboration within parapsychology. Br. J. Psychol. 97, 313–322. doi: 10.1348/000712605X80704

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schooler, J. W., Baumgart, S., and Franklin, M. (2018). Entertaining without endorsing: the case for the scientific investigation of anomalous cognition. Psychol. Conscious. 5, 63–77. doi: 10.1037/cns0000151

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schwartz, S. (2001). The Alexandria project. Bloomington: IUniverse.

Google Scholar

Schwartz, S. (2007). Opening to the infinite. Virginia Beach: Nemoseen Media.

Google Scholar

Sheldrake, R. (2004). “Animal psi” in Parapsychology: Research on exceptional experiences. ed. J. Henry (London: Routledge).

Google Scholar

Sherwood, S. J., and Roe, C. A. (2003). A review of dream ESP studies conducted since the Maimonides dream ESP programme. J. Conscious. Stud. 10, 85–109.

Google Scholar

Simmons, J. P., Nelson, L. D., and Simonsohn, U. (2011). False-positive psychology undisclosed flexibility in data collection and analysis allows presenting anything as significant. Psychol. Sci. 22, 1359–1366. doi: 10.1177/0956797611417632

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Simmonds-Moore, C. A., Alvarado, C. S., and Zingrone, N. L. (2019). A survey exploring synesthetic experiences: exceptional experiences, schizotypy, and psychological well-being. Psychol. Conscious. 6, 99–121. doi: 10.1037/cns0000165

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, M. (2003). The role of the experimenter in parapsychological research. J. Conscious. Stud. 10, 69–84.

Google Scholar

Storm, L., Tressoldi, P., and Risio, L. D. (2010). Meta-analysis of free-response studies, 1992–2008: assessing the noise reduction model in parapsychology. Psychol. Bull. 136, 471–485. doi: 10.1037/a0019457

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Thalbourne, M. A. (2000). Transliminality: a review. Int. J. Parapsychol. 11, 1–34.

Google Scholar

Tressoldi, P. E., and Utts, J. (2015). “Statistical guidelines for empirical studies” in Parapsychology: A handbook for the 21st century. eds. E. Cardeña, J. Palmer, and D. Marcusson-Clavertz (Jefferson: McFarland).

Google Scholar

Utts, J. (1996). An assessment of the evidence for psychic functioning. J. Sci. Explor. 10, 3–30. doi: 10.30891/jopar.2018.03.10

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Utts, J., and Tressoldi, P. E. (2019). Invited editorial methodological and statistical recommendations: option or necessity? J. Parapsychol. 83, 120–122. doi: 10.30891/jopar.2019.02.02

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wagenmakers, E. -J., Wetzels, R., Borsboom, D., Kievit, R. A., and van der Maas, H. L. (2015). “A skeptical eye on psi” in Extrasensory perception: Support, skepticism, and science. eds. E. C. May and S. B. Marwaha (Westport: Praeger).

Google Scholar

Wagenmakers, E., Wetzels, R., Borsboom, D., and Van der Maas, H. (2011). Why psychologists must change the way they analyze their data: the case of psi: comment on Bem (2011). J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 100, 426–432. doi: 10.1037/a0022790

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Walach, H., Horan, M., Hinterberger, T., and von Lucadou, W. (2019). Evidence for anomalistic correlations between human behavior and a random event generator: result of an independent replication of a micro-PK experiment. Psychol. Conscious. 7, 173–188. doi: 10.1037/cns0000199

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Walach, H., and von Stillfried, N. (2011). Generalised quantum theory—basic idea and general intuition: a background story and overview. Axiomathes 21, 185–209. doi: 10.1007/s10516-010-9145-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Watt, C., and Kennedy, J. E. (2017). Options for prospective meta-analysis and introduction of registration-based prospective meta-analysis. Front. Psychol. 7:2030. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.02030

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Watt, C., and Kennedy, J. E. (2019). The American statistician special issue on statistical inference. J. Parapsychol. 83, 283–285. doi: 10.30891/jopar.2019.02.14

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

West, D. J., and Fisk, G. W. (1953). A dual ESP experiment with clock cards. J. Soc. Psychol. Res. 37, 185–197.

Google Scholar

Wiggins, B. J., and Chrisopherson, C. D. (2019). The replication crisis in psychology: an overview for theoretical and philosophical psychology. J. Theor. Philos. Psychol. 39, 202–217. doi: 10.1037/teo0000137

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wiseman, R. (2010). Heads i win, tails you lose: how parapsychologists nullify null results. Skeptical Inquirer 34, 36–39.

Google Scholar

Witte, E. H., and Zenker, F. (2017). From discovery to justification: outline of an ideal research program in empirical psychology. Front. Psychol. 8:1847. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01847

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Articles You May Like

Jessica Knight and Alden Parker: The Romance That Could Change NCIS Forever
Watch Hozier Cover the Pogues’ ‘Fairytale of New York’ on ‘Saturday Night Live’
Paris Hilton and Husband Carter Reum’s Relationship Timeline
Trailer: An Emotional Story On ‘THE LAST JOURNEY’
The Best Art Galleries to Visit in London